Sophists | Encyclopedia.com (2024)

In English, the term sophist is most often used pejoratively, for one who argues with devious abuses of logic. The Greek Sophistês took on a similar sense in the fifth century BCE., but its original meaning is simply expert or wise person. In the study of Greek philosophy, the sophists denote a group of teachers and intellectuals of the fifth and fourth century BCE (the term is also used for later practitioners of their profession; this soon comes to be interchangeable with rhetoric or public speaking, as in the so-called Second Sophistic movement of the second century CE).

The sophists are perennially ambiguous and controversial figures, and it has long been debated whether they should be deemed philosophers. Two central points seem clear: First, the sophists did not constitute a philosophical school with a shared set of metaphysical and ethical positions; second, a number of them did develop serious, innovative, and influential ideas and arguments on a wide range of topics, and so demand inclusion in the history of ancient philosophy.

The sophists are best seen as an intellectual movement, comparable to the philosophies of the eighteenth century or the progressive thinkers of Victorian England (some of whom, such as George Grote, were champions of the ancient sophists). As always with such movements, it is debatable who should be counted as a member, and membership is in any case more a matter of shared interests and tendencies than common doctrines. The leading figures of the sophistic movement so understood include Protagoras, Gorgias, Hippias, Antiphon, and Prodicus. Gorgias was primarily a rhetorician (i.e., an expert in and teacher of public speaking), but the two professions must have overlapped widely, and his surviving texts are among the most important for reconstructing sophistic ideas. Socrates was often counted among the sophists by his contemporaries, and is used to represent the whole movement in Aristophanes' Clouds ; in a number of dialogues Plato aims to show that he differs from them radically.

Sophistic ideas have also come from some important anonymous texts, such as the Dissoi Logoi and the Anonymus Iamblichi (a long discussion of virtue, apparently of sophistic origin, inserted by the Neoplatonist Iamblichus in his Protrepticus ), or of contested authorship (notably the fragment on religion from the satyr play Sisyphus, attributed to both Critias and Euripides).

They can also be found in contemporary historical and medical texts (e.g., Thucydides' Melian Dialogues, the Hippocratic On the Art ), as well as comedy and tragedy (especially Euripides). So there is no firm dividing line between sophistic thought and the broader fifth-century Greek culture around them, which was marked by a vigorous questioning of tradition and empirical, naturalistic researches into many subjects (historiê ).

Sociologically, the sophists were professional teachers, the first in Greece to offer a higher education in the liberal arts. Sophists (who came from all over the Greek world) traveled from city to city presenting themselves to prospective students through public displays; this could involve giving a set speech (epideixis ), performing feats of memory, undertaking to answer any question the audience might pose, or offering question-and-answer refutations of others. This practice of refutation, usually given the pejorative name eristic, is formally identical to the Socratic elenchus ; to differentiate the two, Plato emphasizes that Socrates argues in pursuit of the truth and moral improvement, whereas sophists argue for victory and for money. Some sophists gave displays at the Olympic games, and the sophistic practices themselves were intensely agonistic.

Plato's Protagoras gives a vivid depiction of a gathering of sophists engaged in argument, banter, and competitive intellectual showing-off. Such sessions served as advertisem*nts to the wealthy young men who made up the audience, encouraging them to sign on for further teaching. This would be an expensive proposition: The sophists (and above all Protagoras) seem to have charged far more than any other contemporary professionals, and became enormously rich from their teaching. Sophists also served on embassies for their native cities, drafted laws, and wrote books; they were famous and influentialand bitterly controversialpublic intellectuals as well as teachers.

Most sophists are said to have claimed to teach virtue (arête ), but their curricula and teaching methods varied. In the Protagoras, Protagoras chides Hippias for forcing students to study subjects like mathematics and astronomy; he himself claims to teach them good judgment (euboulia ), enabling them both to manage their private affairs and to succeed in politics, and accepts that this amounts to the teaching of virtue. He also claims that the greatest part of education is the ability to analyze and criticize poetry. So the sophistic teaching of virtue was not a matter of moralistic indoctrination; rather, the sophists taught their students to reflect on traditional values, to analyze and criticize the literary texts that discussed them, and to apply this learning in a political career.

In practice, their teaching seems to have centered on rhetoric or public speaking (hence the blurriness of the line between rhetorician and sophist), which was the key skill for a political career. The connection between teaching rhetoric and teaching virtue is easier to understand if we bear in mind the traditional, Homeric sense of arête as excellencethat is, the skills and personal qualities that make a gentleman successful in his career and a valuable asset to his community. By teaching the arts of political success, the sophists were teaching virtue in a quite traditional sense. In doing so they prompted debate about just what virtue or excellence really consists in, and in particular about the status of qualities such as justice, dikaiosunê, which seem to benefit the community at the expense of their possessor.

The evidence for sophistic ideas is uneven and very defective. There are several brief, but substantial, works by Gorgias (On Not Being ; Defense of Helen ), and a few pages worth of Antiphon's On Truth ; but for Protagoras, the leading figure of the movement, only a handful of brief fragments (that is, trustworthy-looking quotations in later authors) survive. Moreover, many of our texts are ambiguous or difficult to interpret. For instance, both the Dissoi Logoi and Antiphon's discussion of justice seem to argue for contradictory conclusions; perhaps they are exercises in antilogikê, opposing arguments, a sophistic genre associated with Protagoras. Gorgias's On Not Being and the Defense of Helen both seem to be exercises in defending the indefensible; whether they also have serious philosophical agendas is still debated.

A further difficulty is posed by the all-important evidence of Plato, who fixed forever the stereotype of the Sophist. Plato vividly depicts sophists in a number of dialogues (Protagoras, Gorgias, Republic [Thrasymachus], Hippias Major and Minor, and Euthydemus ), and the Sophist is devoted to defining their nature. But Plato's evidence is not consistent: For instance, the Protagoras and the Euthydemus give very different pictures of sophistic argument, and the Protagoras and Theaetetus seem to give conflicting accounts of Protagoras's ethical views. Moreover, Plato's presentation of the sophists is sometimes warped by hostile prejudice (though, as Grote [1865] and T.H. Irwin [1995] have noted, he is not as uniformly hostile as scholars sometimes assume), and by his anxiety to distinguish them as sharply as possible from Socrates.

Unsurprisingly, given the focus of their teaching, sophistic thought seems to have centered on ethical and political topics. However, sophistic interests varied greatly; in some cases they were very broad, and several sophists are associated with ideas in mathematics or natural science. So the traditional scholarly contrast between the sophists and the pre-socratics, with their researches into natural science, is probably misguided or at least overstated. The sophists also were founders of what are now called the social sciences; they offered theories of the origins of human institutions such as law and religion, and took a particular scientific interest in language and the norms applicable to it. Here in the social realm, the closest thing to a unifying pattern in sophistic thought is foundtheir concern to distinguish phusis and nomos (i.e., the natural and the merely conventional or, as one might now say, socially constructed).

Surviving sophistic texts analyze a wide range of human institutions and valuesabove all, justicein these terms, with the assumption that nature represents a deeper or more binding norm than convention. Combined with the sophists' recognition of the differing norms of various cultures (see the Dissoi Logoi ) and their skepticism about traditional religion, this privileging of the natural could be seen as undermining the authority of moral tradition. However, hostility toward the sophists probably had less to do with their particular theories than with their teaching to all comers the ability to speak persuasively, and with it the power to manipulate both political assemblies and legal proceedings.

It is now generally recognized that it is wrong to describe the sophists collectively as moral skeptics, immoralists, or relativists (Bett 1989, 2002). Protagoras is presented as a relativist in Plato's Theaetetus, but not in his earlier and probably more historically accurate Protagoras. The Dissoi Logoi presents a wealth of evidence for the cultural relativity of values, but argues against relativistic conclusions as well as for them. Sophistic uses of nomos and phusis were often in the service of conflicting ethical and political theories, and attempts to pin the sophists down to any common moral theory are doomed by the sheer diversity of sophistic thought. If anything, the sophists (as one would expect given the competitive character of their profession) tended to take up positions in opposition to each othereven if the battle lines are often now blurred by the incompleteness of evidence available.

On matters of natural science, metaphysics, and epistemology, it is still more difficult to identify shared sophistic positions. Antiphon's On Truth seems to have offered a complete cosmogony on natural science: Aristotle, in Physics, reports him as claiming that the true essence of a wooden bed is wood because if planted it would reproduce a tree rather than another bed. Presumably the force of the scientific part of the work was to spell out this kind of distinction between the underlying natures of things (the realm of phusis ) and merely superficial human arrangements and projections, (nomos ).

Gorgias's On Not Being seems intended to support a skeptical conclusion, at least as a critique of metaphysicians like Parmenides. His main criticism was: If beings do have a real nature independent of humans, it can neither be known or communicated. Plato's Theaetetus attributes a sophisticated relativism or subjectivism in epistemology (and ethics) to Protagoras: its slogan, "Man is the measure of all things," must go back to Protagoras's work Truth, but how much of the detailed theory presented by Plato that is genuinely Protagorean is uncertain. Even setting aside other sophistic views (where evidence is even scantier), the most these positions could be said to share is a critical orientationa tendency to diagnose beliefs and perceptions (both everyday and scientific, or philosophical) as irreducibly subjective.

In keeping with their activities as teachers and writers, and their interest in the analysis of human conventions, the sophists were noted for their researches into language. Prodicus was celebrated for drawing fine distinctions in the meanings of words. It is thought that Protagoras analyzed the parts of speech, and claimed that the words for wrath and helmet, feminine in Greek, were properly masculine. The sophists are often associated with claims that falsehood and contradiction are impossible, but the evidence for this is unclear and confusing, and these claims are hard to square with the eristic practice of inducing contradictions in others. One might suspect that distinctive views about the nature of truth were entailed by Protagoras's Measure Thesis, and lay behind his practice of argument on both sides of a question (antilogikê ); but attempts to reconstruct sophistic ideas on these questions are highly speculative.

See also Antiphon; Gorgias of Leontini; Nomos and Phusis; Protagoras of Abdera; Socrates.

Bibliography

Barney, R. "The Sophistic Movement." In The Blackwell Companion to Ancient Philosophy, edited by Mary Louise Gill and Pierre Pellegrin. Oxford: Blackwell, 2005.

Bett, R. "Is There a Sophistic Ethics?" Ancient Philosophy 22 (2002): 235262.

Bett, R. "The Sophists and Relativism." Phronesis 34 (1989): 139169.

Broadie, Sarah. "The Sophists and Socrates." In The Cambridge Companion to Greek and Roman Philosophy, edited by D.N. Sedley. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2003.

Diels, H. Die fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 6th ed. revised by W. Kranz. Berlin: Weidmann, 19511952.

Dillon, J., and T. Gergel. The Greek Sophists. Penguin, 2003.

Gagarin, M., and P. Woodruff. Early Greek Political Thought from Homer to the Sophists. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1995.

Grote, George. A History of Greece, 4th ed. London: John Murray, 1872.

Grote, George. Plato and the Other Companions of Socrates. London: John Murray, 1865.

Guthrie, W.K.C. A History of Greek Philosophy. Vol. 3. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1969.

Irwin, T.H. "Plato's Objections to the Sophists." In The Greek World, edited by C.A. Powell. London: Routledge, 1995.

Kerferd, G.B. The Sophistic Movement. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1981.

Morrison, J. S. "The Truth of Antiphon." Phronesis 8 (1963): 3549.

Nehamas, A. "Eristic, Antilogic, Sophistic, Dialectic: Plato's Demarcation of Philosophy from Sophistry." History of Philosophy Quarterly 7 (1990): 316.

Pendrick, G. Antiphon The Sophist: The Fragments. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2002.

Robinson, T.M., ed. Contrasting Arguments: an Edition of the Dissoi Logoi. New York: Arno Press, 1979.

Sidgwick, Henry. "The Sophists." Journal of Philology (1872): 288307.

Sidgwick, Henry. "The Sophists." Journal of Philology (1873): 6680.

Striker, G. "Methods of Sophistry." In Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

Waterfield, R. The First Philosophers: The Presocratics and Sophists. Oxford: Oxford Paperbacks, 2000.

Rachel Barney (2005)

Sophists | Encyclopedia.com (2024)

FAQs

What was the main idea of Sophists? ›

They were secular atheists, relativists and cynical about religious beliefs and all traditions. They believed and taught that "might makes right". They were pragmatists trusting in whatever works to bring about the desired end at whatever the cost.

Did Sophists believe in God? ›

Arguing that 'man is the measure of all things', the Sophists were skeptical about the existence of the gods and taught a variety of subjects, including mathematics, grammar, physics, political philosophy, ancient history, music, and astronomy.

Who are the Sophists today? ›

In today's society, lawyers are the true modern Sophists — arguers for hire. And the court is their battleground where they try to outshine each other in a dazzling show of Sophistry!

What does Plato say about Sophists? ›

The Sophist in Plato is the master of the art of illusion; the charlatan, the foreigner, the prince of esprits-faux, the hireling who is not a teacher, and who, from whatever point of view he is regarded, is the opposite of the true teacher.

What were the moral teachings of the Sophists? ›

The sophists believed morality was an a priori fact of existence, denouncing Platonic and Aristotelian nomocratic relativism. They outlined a new framework of ethics; a framework which transcends human convention and custom.

What was the problem with the Sophists? ›

Isocrates' Criticism of the Sophists

The first accusation is that sophists make big promises that they cannot fulfill, especially relating to having the ability to teach the virtue and justice. The inconsistency between what the sophists claim to teach and their actual ability is Isocrates' second point.

What is another word for Sophists? ›

sophist (noun as in hypocrite) Strongest matches. bigot charlatan crook impostor phony trickster.

What is an example of a sophistry? ›

An example of sophistry is the argument that cutting people is a crime, and since doctors cut people open, doctors commit crimes. This is the sophistry of the irrelevant conclusion.

Why does Socrates not believe in God? ›

Socrates also believes in deity, but his conception is completely different from the typical Athenians. While to the Athenians gods are human-like and confused, Socrates believes god to be perfectly good and perfectly wise. His god is rationally moral. His god also has a purpose.

Who is the greatest sophist in existence? ›

Protagoras of Abdera (c. 490-420 B.C.E.) was the most prominent member of the sophistic movement and Plato reports he was the first to charge fees using that title (Protagoras, 349a).

What is the difference between a philosopher and a sophist? ›

Plato sought to distinguish sophists from philosophers, arguing that a sophist was a person who made his living through deception, whereas a philosopher was a lover of wisdom who sought the truth. To give the philosophers greater credence, Plato gave the sophists a negative connotation.

Did Sophists believe in absolute truth? ›

Absolutely not, said the Sophists.

What is the famous phrase of Sophists? ›

A key text is the famous 'Man the Measure' sentence, the opening sentence of his work entitled 'Truth', which runs 'Man is the measure of all things, of the things that are that they are and of the things that are not that they are not' (Plato, Theaetetus 151e, Sextus Against the Mathematicians VII.

Who was the first sophist? ›

In Plato's Protagoras (317c) he says that he is old enough to be the father of anyone present, including Hippias and Prodicus. This confirms that he was one of the earliest sophists and suggests the 490s BCE as his birth year.

What did the Sophists believe about reality? ›

Answer: The Sophists viewed reality as ever-changing and malleable, emphasizing the power of rhetoric and the persuasive abilities of the human person. They rejected the notion of absolute truth and morality, instead advocating for the ability of humans to alter reality through persuasive discourse.

Did the Sophists aim to persuade? ›

The purpose of these works is primarily to display skill in intellectual argument, as well as to give pleasure. Persuasion may be a goal of some sophistic works, but it is not their primary goal; and teaching the art of persuasion was not a major concern of the Sophists.

What did the Sophists believe about natural law? ›

Sophists, states that it has often been said that "there are as many forms of law as there are governments"; that the laws have to consider "only the interest and the power and the pres- ervation of the established form of government," for this is considered by the many "to be the best way of expressing the natural ...

What did the Sophists claim to teach their students? ›

Even if, as their detractors claim, these were their only goals, the Sophists bolstered rhetorical training with a well-rounded curriculum that included instruction in grammar; the nature of virtue and the bases of morality; the history of society and the arts; poetry, music, and mathematics; and astronomy and the ...

References

Top Articles
Latest Posts
Article information

Author: Dong Thiel

Last Updated:

Views: 6303

Rating: 4.9 / 5 (59 voted)

Reviews: 90% of readers found this page helpful

Author information

Name: Dong Thiel

Birthday: 2001-07-14

Address: 2865 Kasha Unions, West Corrinne, AK 05708-1071

Phone: +3512198379449

Job: Design Planner

Hobby: Graffiti, Foreign language learning, Gambling, Metalworking, Rowing, Sculling, Sewing

Introduction: My name is Dong Thiel, I am a brainy, happy, tasty, lively, splendid, talented, cooperative person who loves writing and wants to share my knowledge and understanding with you.